Hans Hoppe gave an in-depth interview to Jeff Deist at the Mises Institute. The entire interview is worth a read, as it covers a wide variety of topics – from Hoppe’s personal history to some of his most controversial writing. In this post I will cover some of the topics that are – and have been – of interest to me in my writing.
Suffice it to say, I truly admire the work that Hoppe has done. This began well before I started this blog, but only grew when I was challenged to challenge Hoppe in the same way that I challenged left-libertarians. I can truly say that taking up this challenge has offered to me one of the handful of meaningful paths that have brought me to my current thought.
With that, let’s begin. Hoppe begins with a look back at his childhood, a child of refugees from East Germany, having fled the Soviet darkness:
Germany had lost a devastating war, and the German population was subjected to a systematic, American-led reeducation campaign, a Charakterwaesche (character-wash), as I was to realize only many years later, of truly enormous proportions, which involved a complete rewriting of history from the victor’s viewpoint, essentially portraying Germans as congenital villains.
Orderly and Humane: Th... Best Price: $16.74 Buy New $20.61 (as of 09:17 UTC - Details) Germans living in the east at the end of World War Two were subject to one of the most brutal forced expulsions in history, with as many as fourteen million forced from their homes and one million killed. I have examined this history via a book by R.M. Douglas, Orderly and Humane: The Expulsion of the Germans after the Second World War. I cover this history with these several posts:
o The “Orderly and Humane” Forced Expulsion of 14 Million Germans
o The Seeds of German Expulsion are Sown
o German Expulsions: Having No Plan IS the Plan
Germans, at Nuremberg, were subjected to trials that made the Soviets proud; Germans were thereafter forced – by law – a to accept a historical narrative of total, complete, and unique guilt for the war; they were thereafter required to reiterate this fiction as a condition for re-unification.
Truth doesn’t need law to defend it; when laws are used to protect against speech or inquiry, it is safe to assume that the laws defend lies. When you find law defending a narrative, it is only proper to believe the exact opposite. It was into just such a world where Hoppe was born.
The next topic of note from the interview is that of the role of Christianity in the development of the West and in the development of the liberty – to the extent we have it – that we enjoy. It cannot be denied that it is in the Christian West where “the idea of natural human rights and human freedom,” as Hoppe puts it, was fully developed.
The Christian notion that each person is created in the image of God contributed to the uniquely Western tradition of individualism and was instrumental in abolishing, at long last, the institution of slavery within the Christian orbit (all the while it lingered on outside the West, even until today).
Without this notion that all men are made in God’s image, on what basis could institutions like slavery be properly abolished? This is not to suggest that all men are created equal – not in any egalitarian sense that the word is used today.
And the institutional separation and jealous competition for social recognition and authority in the West between the Christian church and its hierarchy of popes, cardinals, bishops, and priests, on the one hand, and all worldly power with its hierarchy of emperors, kings, nobles, and heads of households on the other contributed greatly to the uniquely Western tradition of limited (as opposed to absolutist) government.
I first came across this idea in Fritz Kern’s, Kingship and Law in the Middle Ages. I have written about this book in the following posts:
o Every Individual Vested with Veto Power
o A Written Constitution: Protecting the State from the People
Kingship and Law in th... Best Price: $46.01 Buy New $50.00 (as of 10:10 UTC - Details) I have further developed this history in several other posts too numerous to list here. The Church and the king were competing authorities, neither fully sovereign and each providing a check upon the other.
Now for one of the more controversial aspects of Hoppe’s work, regarding Hoppe’s views about physically removing those who have goals and lifestyles that would destroy a libertarian social order:
This harks back to your earlier question concerning Hoppephobia. The whole affair, most likely initiated by one of the usual left-libertarian suspects from the DC beltway, was a deliberate attempt to smear and malign me personally and with that also the program of a realistic or right-libertarianism first outlined in the book.
I am certain that this was the intent of the individual who first challenged me to challenge Hoppe; if I ever come across this individual, I will truly thank him for starting me on this aspect of my journey.
Essentially, I did not say anything more controversial or scandalous in the short passage than that anyone insisting on wearing a bathing suit on a nude beach may be expelled from this beach (but be free to look for another one), just as anyone insisting on nudity may be expelled from a formal dinner party (but be free to look for another party).
Yes. Such examples – at least at this moment in time – are not considered scandalous by today’s standards of wokesterism.
In my example, however, it was not nudes but homosexuals that figured. I wrote that in a covenant established for the purpose of protecting family and kin, people openly displaying and habitually promoting homosexuality may be expelled and compelled to look for another place to live. But in some “woke” circles, mentioning homosexuality and expulsion in one and the same sentence apparently leads to intellectual blank-out and a loss of all reading comprehension.
This is unfortunate, and more so when it is the view taken by those who otherwise might be considered philosophical allies. Walter Block is, unfortunately, one of these. I have addressed this issue in the past, where Block (and other critics of Hoppe’s view) ignore the conditions set by Hoppe in his example where he explicitly writes:
In a covenant concluded among proprietor and community tenants for the purpose of protecting their private property…. Likewise, in a covenant founded for the purpose of protecting family and kin…
What is so complicated about “my property, my rules”? In any case, Block now offers a more recent example, addressing Hoppe’s supposedly anti-libertarian view on private property and community:
To wit, he should have written here removal from a condo, or from a voluntary association, or from a club, not from “society” as a whole
I don’t even know what this objection means or how it applies to Hoppe’s example. Hoppe was explicit about the “society” from which such people must be expelled, he was not writing about “society as a whole,” whatever that means – the world, the hemisphere, the continent? Are they to be sent to the moon? Not according to Hoppe.
In any case, in my earlier post I addressed all of this – and shared it with Block. I need say no more, other than it would be good if this mischaracterization by those who consider themselves allies with Hoppe would stop.
Next is the highly controversial (within libertarian circles and almost nowhere else) issue of immigration and open-borders. I have written dozens of posts examining this question (look for the word immigration or borders on this page for a sampling). Hoppe offers the most libertarian view, yet is demonized as a xenophobe. To begin, what Hoppe says about “immigration” in a completely private property order cannot be denied by any libertarian:
Ideally, with all pieces of land and everything on them privately owned, there would be a huge variety of entrance requirements, i.e., of degrees, respectively, of openness and closedness. …all migration would be by invitation and invariably the full cost principle would apply.
In a world of private property, borders would be “managed,” not “open.” This is so obvious on its face that it is mind-boggling that libertarians don’t get it.
Is it not up to the property owner – whether a private home or business – to decide the entrance requirements for those whishing to enter? Would libertarians require, by force, open borders to private property? Would libertarians support forcing others to pay the cost of such access? Laughable.
Either the inviting host or the invited guest or both jointly would have to pay the full cost associated with the guest’s presence. No cost could be shifted and externalized onto third parties, and the inviter and/or invitee would be held liable for any and all damage resulting from the invitation to the property of others.
In a world (or community) of fully private property, would this not be the case? Yet, since we do not live in a world of complete private property, what would be the most libertarian position in our world, a world of state borders? What “policy” would come closest to mimicking this perfectly libertarian policy?
If and as long as there is a state with so-called public property in place, as happens to be the case in today’s world, then the best one may hope for is an immigration policy that tries to approach this ideal of a natural order.
I have written of this policy: it would be one of invitation, where the one doing the inviting would take on any liability generated by the one invited – up to and including being held liable for any crimes committed.
Further…
…in today’s world the sometimes mentioned “wilderness” of mountaintops, swamps, tundra, etc., is no longer truly wild and thus ready to be homesteaded.
Of course, in practice, immigrants don’t go to such places. Yet, the proper objection is even more fundamental:
There is no inch left on earth today that is not claimed to be the “property” of some government. Whatever wilderness there is, then, it is wilderness that has been barred and prevented by some government, i.e., with taxpayer funds, from being homesteaded by private parties (most likely by neighboring property owners). If anyone, it is domestic taxpayers who are the legitimate owners of such wilderness.
Every square inch of government-controlled land has been “improved,” to a more or less degree, by the government using money appropriated from the taxpayer. Libertarian theory would hold, unequivocally, that it is the taxpayer who is the rightful owner of the government-controlled property.
It was the stolen property from the taxpayer that paid for the improvements of government-controlled property. Justice requires a return of stolen property to its rightful owner. In other words, there is no unowned wilderness lands.
From these realities (private property is managed, not open; there is no unowned wilderness), proper libertarian conclusions can be reached regarding immigration and borders in a world of state-controlled property.
Finally, regarding Hoppe’s argumentation ethics. The presuppositions of Hoppe’s position are as follows:
…first, each person is entitled to exclusive control or ownership of his physical body (that he and only he can control directly, at will) so as to act independently of others and come to a conclusion on his own. And secondly, for the same reason of mutually independent standing or autonomy, both proponent and opponent must be entitled to their respective prior possessions, i.e., the exclusive control of all other, external means of action appropriated indirectly by them prior to and independent of one another.
Hoppe does not see this as replacing the natural law argument for liberty; it is an argument for those who do not hold to a natural law, objective value in ethics:
In response to the relativist proponent it is essentially pointed out that by virtue of his own engagement in argumentation he has already effectively rejected his own thesis, because argumentation is an activity, a special, conflict-free form of interaction between a proponent and an opponent with the specific purpose of clarifying and possibly coming to a mutual agreement concerning some rival truth claims.
I have read and considered Hoppe’s argumentation ethics in the past, including arguments for and against by others; I don’t recall ever coming across a more concise and clearly worded explanation of its purpose. He does not view it as a replacement for natural law; it is a complement for those who will deny an objective natural law. In other words, it is an answer for the ethical relativist.
Conclusion
There is much more to the interview, and I thank Jeff Deist and the Mises Institute for bringing it to us; I especially thank Hans Hoppe for sharing his time with us.
Reprinted with permission from Bionic Mosquito.